A Truly Pernicious Book: Revisiting Hannah Arendt
By JOSHUA HALBERSTAM
EICHMANN IN JERUSALEM
A Report on the Banality of Evil
By Hannah Arendt
312 pages. Penguin Classics. $15.00.
The
ascription screams calumny, hyperbole surely, yet I aver: this book has arguably
wreaked more lasting moral havoc that any other of the last fifty years.
Let me hasten to explain my criteria for this unwelcome laurel. By “pernicious”
I don’t mean “wicked.” Wicked
are books such as Mein Kampf and its
endless procession of clones; Eichmann in
Jerusalem is certainly not loathsome in that sense, neither in its
intention nor product. But where Hitler’s execrable screed had but marginal
effect—its publication a burning match flicked into an already blazing inferno
of fascist hatred—Arendt’s book, and in particular, the thesis of its subtitle,
“A Report on the Banality of Evil,” has provided intellectual cover for what
has become a dominant approach to evil. An approach, I submit, that is
philosophically insupportable, psychologically hollow, morally invidious, and
politically menacing.
But let’s first clear away the many beckoning asides. This lament is not about
Hannah Arendt. These past months, numerous articles have appeared celebrating
the 100th anniversary of her birth… and deservedly so. Arendt was a
provocative political thinker whose analysis of totalitarianism remains
influential, original, and prescient. There are, of course, too, the well-known
blotches in her personal life, especially the amorous relationship with her
mentor, Martin Heidegger, with whom she renewed friendly contact after the war
despite his unrepentant Nazi affiliations. More demanding of our attention,
though not the present point either, is the chorus of infelicities regarding
Arendt’s Eichmanntext itself. The
book’s provenance began as “reportage” on the 1961 Eichmann trial for the New Yorker magazine, and its publication
as a book in 1963 sparked immediate and longstanding controversy. Historians
railed about Arendt’s many misrepresentations—her “somewhat cavalier attitude
toward the facts,” as Walter Laqueur
politely complained. Jurists argued with Arendt’s persistent cavil with regard
to Israel’s legal standing to hear the case and the court’s subsequent
procedures. But the most vociferous anger was directed at Arendt’s portrayal of
Jewish leadership and, in particular, her claim that the Judenrat
was morally complicit with the German authorities. Her judgmental tone struck
many as so lacking in compassion as to border on cruelty; Arendt’s erstwhile
friend Gershom Sholem famously wrote to her that, at root, she lacked ahavat yisroel, a love of her fellow
Jews. On rereading Eichmann in Jerusalem,
one is driven to agree: for Jews, this is an ugly book. But, ugly, too, is not
necessarily pernicious.
However, the concept of evil as a banality is
pernicious. In insisting that Eichmann was mentally and moral normal, your
everyday Hans, Arendt posited a view of evil that cohered with her larger
theory about the mechanization of modern technologies. The perpetrators of
destruction, she suggested, are but thoughtless cogs in the institutional
churning. Evil has become routinized, not personal, and individual
intentionality is no longer salient in establishing blame. This conception has
now been distilled into commonplace platitudes: “There’s a Nazi lurking in all
of us.” Or, “Given the relevant circumstances, we are all capable of
participating in mass murder.” Why would a billionaire order his minions to fly
planes into tall buildings? Suicide bombers blow up children in mosques?
Jihadists slice the throats of infidels? Corporate pirates steal millions?
According to the current cliché, it’s because they’re all “caught up” in some
system. And so we are permitted to proffer what underlying explanation we
will—poverty, injustice, humiliation, bad parenting—any hypothesis whatsoever,
but never the straightforward notion of a genuine human choice to commit evil.
But evil is a choice. And it is personal. And intentions do count—including the
decision to work for malevolent institutions. And we aren’t all latent
torturers or mindless bureaucrats—“little Eichmanns,” as one asinine academic
called the victims in the Twin Towers. Indeed, the facts about Eichmann
chronicled by his serious biographers reveal someone far from the commonplace corporate
climber that Arendt presents. Even before Hitler had arrived on the scene,
Eichmann had joined a fascist, anti-Semitic organization and his subsequent
career was studded with a relentless eagerness to expedite the annihilation of
the Jews. He was not ordinary, but extraordinarily malicious throughout his
adulthood. To Arendt, Eichmann’s oft-repeated assertion that he’d “jump
laughing into his grave because he had the death of five million Jews on his
conscience,” was the mere boasting of a thoughtless, ambitious apparatchik, but
all the evidence suggest he certainly meant what he said.
The cliché about the banality of evil is often reinforced with a reference to
the renowned Milgram experiments which demonstrated
how easy it was to get people to administer “supposed” shocks when ordered to
do so. But the breathless extrapolation one learns in psych classes from the
willingness to follow a Yale professor’s exhortation to a willingness to serve
as a commandant at Auschwitz is ludicrous. (Note that the subjects of these
experiments were always assured that these shocks would produce no lasting harm
and when the experiment was replicated outside the confines of the university,
the majority of subjects refused to comply.)
Columns of determinist schemas have paraded down the centuries attempting to
“explain away” evil as something other than individual choice. We’ve had
appeals to misaligned stars and incarnations of the devil, to more recent references
to imbalances in economies and class. To this list, we can add Arendt’s
speculations about technological totalitarianism. On the horizon is the
emerging field of “neuroethics,” which locates moral decisions in the
hardwiring of the brain. Showing just why all these reductionist moves confuse
cause and effect is a complex philosophical challenge. In the end, individual
ethical choice will remain on center stage.
Why are so many now drawn to this idea of evil as banal? For one thing, evil’s
perpetrators do seem like regular folk—we’re always surprised when that nice
next-door neighbor turns out to be the serial pederast. But what do we expect
the Eichmanns of the world to look like? Monsters with gnarled claws and blood
dripping down their fangs? Conversely, heroes too walk our streets without
telltale halos hovering above them. It is, after all, otherwise ordinary people
who commit acts of exceptional horror or exceptional good. But that hardly
renders as banal either their actions or their moral character.
Hannah Arendt, let me repeat, was a subtle writer who thought hard about the
existence of evil, and she certainly is not wholly responsible for the
widespread attitude about evil which traces to her controversial book (though
she’s not entirely innocent here either). But whatever the prompt, we
desperately need to cease promoting these catechisms that proclaim moral
equivalency everywhere, this systemic flattening of moral differences. The
nobility of the human enterprise entails the recognition that each of us is
capable of outstanding good or bad. Alas, reciting the easy mantra about “the
banality of evil” has itself become an evil banality.