Spinoza: The Marrano of Reason
By YIRMIYAHU YOVEL
On July 27, 1656, a sentence of excommunication was
pronounced on a 24-year-old Jew of the Portuguese community of Amsterdam and
recorded in the communal record book. The object of this excommunication, Baruch
d’Espinoza, belonged to the upper crust of the Jewish community. The young
Baruch (Bento) received a traditional Jewish education, and also read
independently on secular subjects. At the age of six he lost his mother, and
from then on death visited the family frequently, taking his younger brother,
his sister, his stepmother, and finally his father.
Spinoza was 22 when his father died. Together with his brother he founded a
commercial company, and during this period, Spinoza continued to attend the Keter
Torah yeshivah headed by Rabbi Shaul Levi Morteira, and apparently kept up his
connection with his former teacher, Rabbi Menasseh ben Israel, whose home was a
center for scholars. On the surface, at least, no change was as yet perceptible
in Spinoza’s relations with the Jewish community.
Nevertheless, he was apparently full of doubts and heretical thoughts. He knew
the Bible by heart and found many contradictions in it. The notion of miracles
seemed to him to contradict both reason and the laws of nature, and in the
prophets he found evidence of great imaginative power but not of ordered
rational thought. The ordinances of the Torah (written law) and the halakah (oral law) seemed to him
arbitrary and merely historical, having nothing to do with the laws of God. If
God did indeed have laws, they could only be inherent in the universe itself,
in the form of the universal and immutable laws of nature. Moreover, in view of
the death that awaits all, there was no comfort in the vain idea of a life to
come. Death was the absolute end of every living creature, of both body and
soul; if there was any value or purpose in
life, it had to be found in this world—in a life of inquiry and
understanding and in the intellectual freedom of the individual. Spinoza still
clung to the idea of the eternal, the infinite, the perfect—in other words, the
idea of God—but this deity was not in his view a unique and separate person
existing outside the world and the nature he had created. God, the object of
man’s love, was rather the universe itself, insofar as it could be grasped as a
single whole. Nature and God were one, and the knowledge of nature was
therefore the knowledge of God.
It is not known when these ideas matured in the mind of the heterodox youth,
but the process apparently began at a rather early age. With these ideas
Spinoza distanced himself from both Judaism and Christianity, and even from the
accepted philosophical tradition; he was a heretic not only from the point of
view of the established religions, but also from the point of view of the
freethinkers and from the several varieties of philosophic deism they were
espousing at the time. Deistic heretics at least acknowledged the existence of
a transcendent deity elevated above the world, whereas Spinoza dismissed this
idea and identified God with the whole of the universe. In short, Spinoza
proclaimed himself a heretic not only among the faithful, but also among
representatives of the accepted heresy of his period.
In its mature form, Spinoza’s system is one of the most important in the
history of philosophy. Although he had few disciples, it has simply not been
possible, ever since the modern republication of his works, to participate in
the enterprise of philosophy without taking his world view into account. In the
words of Henri Bergson, “Every philosopher has two philosophies: his own and
Spinoza’s.”
Spinoza’s ethics and metaphysics–the essence of his teaching—were not his first
achievements. They were preceded by a profound critique of religion and a
vigorous attacks on its sacred texts—first and foremost the Bible. When he
wrote this critique, the young Spinoza, who did not know Latin, had not yet
read the new scientific and philosophical works that would change the face of
the age. He had not come into contact with the students of Descartes and the
scholars of the Royal Society of London, and was not acquainted with Hobbes,
Machiavelli, or Galileo. He developed his reflections and criticisms of
religion solely from within the world of contemporary Judaism.
The Jews of Amsterdam in Spinoza’s time have been described both in literary
works and by historians (mainly those following Heinrich Graetz) as a
narrow-minded and fanatical lot who deliberately shut themselves off from any
spark of enlightenment from the outside world. This picture is inaccurate. The
truth of the matter is that the Amsterdam community was one of the most
enlightened and cosmopolitan Jewish communities of the period. The people who
inhabited Amsterdam’s Jewish Street—which was worlds apart from the closed
ghettos of eastern Europe—were former Marranos or sons of Marranos, most of
them prosperous businessmen living in relative freedom within a tolerant state.
Engaged mainly in import and export and other forms of international commerce,
they were accustomed to mingling with non-Jews and were open-minded and
receptive, having been educated in the schools of Spain and Portugal, or later
the flourishing educational system developed by the Amsterdam community itself.
At the same time, their experience as former Marranos was a never-ending source
of perplexity to them, an experience that led to difficulties of adjustment and
deep-seated problems of identity. It is against this background that one must
view both Spinoza’s heresy and the excommunication that was its result.
Some have seen in the Marranos the “beginning of modernization in Europe.” Even
without going so far, however, it is clear that a person who had been educated
as a Christian and who then chose to return to Judaism could not belong
entirely or simply to either faith. Spinoza would of necessity be faced with
enormous difficulties in reintegrating himself into the community to which he
indeed belonged, but whose daily life and deepest values and symbols were not
actually part of his experience. It is not hard to understand how a man who is
neither Christian nor Jew, but who is divided between the two or who possesses
memories of the one existing within the other, might be inclined to develop
doubts about both, or even to question the foundations of religion altogether.
As Yosef Yerushalmi has argued, the wonder is not that the return of the
Marranos to Judaism gave rise to doubts and heresies, but rather that the
majority should have succeeded as far as they did in reintegrating themselves
into the framework of normative Judaism. In any case, Spinoza did not lack
predecessors in his heresy among the Marranos—the dough of “New Jews” seems to
have contained a leavening agent that gave rise to a constant intellectual
ferment from within.
It is widely claimed that Spinoza’s critique of religion was influenced above
all by his reading of Jewish philosophy. But why should the boy have pored over
ancient Jewish texts and extracted from them elements that might have sounded
heretical out of context unless there was some incentive in his external
environment? There is no doubt that Spinoza’s apostasy contained an element of
spontaneous awakening—that spiritual breakthrough of solitary genius which can
not be full explained by a set of foregoing events. Yet this breakthrough did
not occur in the void but within a specific social and cultural milieu, which
must be taken into account if one is to understand the phenomena of Spinoza at
all.
This
excerpt from Spinoza and
Other Heretics, Volume 1: The Marrano of Reason (Princeton University Press, 1989) is reprinted with permission from
the publisher (http://press.princeton.edu/titles/4433.html).